Which Individuals Are Credited With Introducing the Concept of a Universal Gaze in Art? Anthro
Aesthetics, or esthetics (), is a branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of beauty and taste, as well equally the philosophy of fine art (its own area of philosophy that comes out of aesthetics).[ane] It examines artful values, often expressed through judgments of taste.[2]
Aesthetics covers both natural and artificial sources of aesthetic experience and judgment. Information technology considers what happens in our minds when we appoint with artful objects or environments such as viewing visual art, listening to music, reading poetry, experiencing a play, or exploring nature. The philosophy of fine art specifically studies how artists imagine, create, and perform works of art, also equally how people employ, enjoy, and criticize fine art. Aesthetics considers why people like some works of art and not others, besides equally how art tin can affect moods or fifty-fifty our beliefs.[3] Both aesthetics and the philosophy of fine art ask questions like "What is fine art?," "What is a piece of work of art?," and "What makes good fine art?"
Scholars in the field accept defined aesthetics as "disquisitional reflection on art, culture and nature".[4] [v] In modern English, the term "aesthetic" tin can likewise refer to a prepare of principles underlying the works of a particular fine art movement or theory (one speaks, for case, of a Renaissance aesthetic).[vi]
Etymology [edit]
The word aesthetic is derived from the Aboriginal Greek αἰσθητικός ( aisthētikós , "perceptive, sensitive, pertaining to sensory perception"), which in plow comes from αἰσθάνομαι ( aisthánomai , "I perceive, sense, learn") and is related to αἴσθησις ( aísthēsis , "perception, sensation").[7] Aesthetics in this central sense has been said to start with the serial of articles on "The Pleasures of the Imagination", which the journalist Joseph Addison wrote in the early issues of the magazine The Spectator in 1712.[8]
The term aesthetics was appropriated and coined with new meaning past the German philosopher Alexander Baumgarten in his dissertation Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis advertising poema pertinentibus (English: "Philosophical considerations of some matters pertaining the poem") in 1735;[9] Baumgarten chose "aesthetics" because he wished to emphasize the experience of art every bit a means of knowing. Baumgarten's definition of aesthetics in the fragment Aesthetica (1750) is occasionally considered the kickoff definition of mod aesthetics.[10]
Aesthetics and the philosophy of art [edit]
Aesthetics is for the artist as ornithology is for the birds.
Some split up aesthetics and the philosophy of art, claiming that the former is the written report of beauty and taste while the latter is the study of works of art. But aesthetics typically considers questions of dazzler equally well equally of art. It examines topics such as art works, aesthetic experience, and artful judgments.[thirteen] Some consider aesthetics to exist a synonym for the philosophy of art since Hegel, while others insist that there is a significant stardom between these closely related fields. In practice, aesthetic judgement refers to the sensory contemplation or appreciation of an object (not necessarily a piece of work of fine art), while artistic judgement refers to the recognition, appreciation or criticism of art or an art piece of work.
Philosophical aesthetics must not just speak about and judge art and art works only likewise define fine art. A common point of disagreement concerns whether art is independent of any moral or political purpose.
Aestheticians weigh a culturally contingent conception of art versus one that is purely theoretical. They study the varieties of art in relation to their physical, social, and cultural environments. Aestheticians also use psychology to understand how people encounter, hear, imagine, think, learn, and act in relation to the materials and problems of art. Aesthetic psychology studies the artistic procedure and the artful experience.[fourteen]
Aesthetic judgment, universals and ethics [edit]
Aesthetic judgment [edit]
Aesthetics examines affective domain response to an object or phenomenon. Judgments of artful value rely on the power to discriminate at a sensory level. Still, aesthetic judgments commonly go across sensory discrimination.
For David Hume, effeminateness of taste is not merely "the power to detect all the ingredients in a composition", just also the sensitivity "to pains as well as pleasures, which escape the rest of mankind."[15] Thus, sensory discrimination is linked to capacity for pleasure.
For Immanuel Kant (Critique of Judgment, 1790), "enjoyment" is the result when pleasance arises from awareness, but judging something to exist "beautiful" has a tertiary requirement: sensation must give rise to pleasance past engaging reflective contemplation. Judgments of beauty are sensory, emotional and intellectual all at in one case. Kant (1790) observed of a man "If he says that canary vino is agreeable he is quite content if someone else corrects his terms and reminds him to say instead: It is agreeable to me," because "Everyone has his ain (sense of) taste". The case of "beauty" is different from mere "agreeableness" because, "If he proclaims something to be beautiful, and so he requires the same liking from others; he then judges not but for himself merely for everyone, and speaks of beauty equally if it were a property of things."
Viewer interpretations of beauty may on occasion be observed to possess two concepts of value: aesthetics and taste. Aesthetics is the philosophical notion of beauty. Taste is a issue of an education process and sensation of elite cultural values learned through exposure to mass culture. Bourdieu examined how the elite in lodge ascertain the aesthetic values like gustation and how varying levels of exposure to these values can result in variations by grade, cultural background, and education.[16] According to Kant, beauty is subjective and universal; thus certain things are beautiful to anybody.[17] In the opinion of Władysław Tatarkiewicz, there are half-dozen conditions for the presentation of fine art: beauty, form, representation, reproduction of reality, artistic expression and innovation. However, i may not exist able to pin down these qualities in a work of art.[xviii]
The question of whether there are facts about aesthetic judgments belongs to the branch of metaphilosophy known as meta-aesthetics.[19]
Factors involved in artful judgment [edit]
Aesthetic sentence is closely tied to disgust. Responses like disgust evidence that sensory detection is linked in instinctual ways to facial expressions including physiological responses like the gag reflex. Disgust is triggered largely by dissonance; as Darwin pointed out, seeing a stripe of soup in a human being's beard is icky even though neither soup nor beards are themselves icky. Aesthetic judgments may exist linked to emotions or, like emotions, partially embodied in physical reactions. For example, the awe inspired by a sublime landscape might physically manifest with an increased heart-rate or pupil dilation.
As seen, emotions are conformed to 'cultural' reactions, therefore aesthetics is e'er characterized by 'regional responses', equally Francis Grose was the first to assert in his 'Rules for Drawing Caricaturas: With an Essay on Comic Painting' (1788), published in W. Hogarth, The Analysis of Beauty, Bagster, London s.d. (1791? [1753]), pp. 1–24. Francis Grose tin therefore exist claimed to exist the first critical 'aesthetic regionalist' in proclaiming the anti-universality of aesthetics in contrast to the perilous and always resurgent dictatorship of beauty.[20] 'Aesthetic Regionalism' tin can thus be seen as a political statement and stance which vies against whatsoever universal notion of beauty to safeguard the counter-tradition of aesthetics related to what has been considered and dubbed un-cute simply because one's civilisation does not contemplate it, east.grand. E. Burke's sublime, what is usually defined as 'archaic' art, or un-harmonious, non-cathartic art, camp fine art, which 'beauty' posits and creates, dichotomously, as its opposite, without even the need of formal statements, but which will be 'perceived' as ugly.[21]
Likewise, aesthetic judgments may be culturally conditioned to some extent. Victorians in United kingdom often saw African sculpture as ugly, merely just a few decades later on, Edwardian audiences saw the aforementioned sculptures as beautiful. Evaluations of dazzler may well be linked to desirability, perhaps even to sexual desirability. Thus, judgments of aesthetic value can become linked to judgments of economic, political, or moral value.[22] In a electric current context, a Lamborghini might be judged to be beautiful partly because it is desirable as a status symbol, or it may exist judged to be repulsive partly because information technology signifies over-consumption and offends political or moral values.[23]
The context of its presentation also affects the perception of artwork; artworks presented in a classical museum context are liked more and rated more interesting than when presented in a sterile laboratory context. While specific results depend heavily on the style of the presented artwork, overall, the result of context proved to exist more than of import for the perception of artwork than the consequence of genuineness (whether the artwork was being presented every bit original or as a facsimile/copy).[24]
Aesthetic judgments can often be very fine-grained and internally contradictory. Likewise artful judgments seem frequently to be at least partly intellectual and interpretative. What a thing means or symbolizes is ofttimes what is being judged. Modernistic aestheticians have asserted that will and desire were well-nigh dormant in aesthetic feel, nevertheless preference and option accept seemed of import aesthetics to some 20th-century thinkers. The point is already made by Hume, but encounter Mary Mothersill, "Beauty and the Critic's Judgment", in The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics, 2004. Thus aesthetic judgments might be seen to be based on the senses, emotions, intellectual opinions, will, desires, culture, preferences, values, subconscious behaviour, conscious decision, preparation, instinct, sociological institutions, or some complex combination of these, depending on exactly which theory is employed.
A third major topic in the study of aesthetic judgments is how they are unified across art forms. For instance, the source of a painting'south dazzler has a different grapheme to that of beautiful music, suggesting their aesthetics differ in kind.[25] The distinct inability of language to express artful judgment and the part of Social structure farther cloud this issue.
Aesthetic universals [edit]
The philosopher Denis Dutton identified 6 universal signatures in human aesthetics:[26]
- Expertise or virtuosity. Humans cultivate, recognize, and admire technical creative skills.
- Nonutilitarian pleasure. People enjoy fine art for art's sake, and practise not need that it keep them warm or put food on the table.
- Style. Artistic objects and performances satisfy rules of composition that place them in a recognizable style.
- Criticism. People make a point of judging, affectionate, and interpreting works of art.
- Imitation. With a few important exceptions like abstract painting, works of art simulate experiences of the earth.
- Special focus. Fine art is set up aside from ordinary life and made a dramatic focus of feel.
Artists such equally Thomas Hirschhorn have indicated that there are too many exceptions to Dutton's categories. For instance, Hirschhorn'due south installations deliberately eschew technical virtuosity. People can appreciate a Renaissance Madonna for artful reasons, but such objects often had (and sometimes however accept) specific devotional functions. "Rules of composition" that might be read into Duchamp's Fountain or John Cage'southward four′33″ do not locate the works in a recognizable style (or certainly non a style recognizable at the time of the works' realization). Moreover, some of Dutton's categories seem too broad: a physicist might entertain hypothetical worlds in his/her imagination in the form of formulating a theory. Another problem is that Dutton'due south categories seek to universalize traditional European notions of aesthetics and fine art forgetting that, as André Malraux and others have pointed out, in that location have been large numbers of cultures in which such ideas (including the idea "art" itself) were non-existent.[27]
Aesthetic ethics [edit]
Aesthetic ethics refers to the idea that human conduct and behaviour ought to be governed by that which is beautiful and attractive. John Dewey[28] has pointed out that the unity of aesthetics and ideals is in fact reflected in our understanding of behaviour being "fair"—the give-and-take having a double significant of bonny and morally acceptable. More than recently, James Page[29] [thirty] has suggested that artful ethics might exist taken to form a philosophical rationale for peace education.
Beauty [edit]
Beauty is one of the main subjects of aesthetics, together with fine art and taste.[31] [32] Many of its definitions include the idea that an object is cute if perceiving it is accompanied by aesthetic pleasure. Among the examples of cute objects are landscapes, sunsets, humans and works of art. Beauty is a positive artful value that contrasts with ugliness as its negative counterpart.[33]
Different intuitions commonly associated with beauty and its nature are in conflict with each other, which poses certain difficulties for understanding information technology.[34] [35] [36] On the one hand, dazzler is ascribed to things equally an objective, public feature. On the other hand, information technology seems to depend on the subjective, emotional response of the observer. It is said, for instance, that "beauty is in the eye of the beholder".[37] [31] It may be possible to reconcile these intuitions past affirming that information technology depends both on the objective features of the beautiful affair and the subjective response of the observer. One style to attain this is to concur that an object is beautiful if it has the ability to bring nearly certain aesthetic experiences in the perceiving subject area. This is often combined with the view that the subject needs to take the power to correctly perceive and estimate beauty, sometimes referred to every bit "sense of gustatory modality".[31] [35] [36] Various conceptions of how to ascertain and understand dazzler have been suggested. Classical conceptions emphasize the objective side of beauty past defining it in terms of the relation betwixt the cute object equally a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus etch an integrated harmonious whole.[31] [33] [36] Hedonist conceptions, on the other hand, focus more on the subjective side by drawing a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for information technology to cause disinterested pleasure.[38] Other conceptions include defining beautiful objects in terms of their value, of a loving mental attitude towards them or of their office.[39] [33] [31]
New Criticism and "The Intentional Fallacy" [edit]
During the first half of the twentieth century, a significant shift to general aesthetic theory took place which attempted to employ aesthetic theory between various forms of art, including the literary arts and the visual arts, to each other. This resulted in the ascent of the New Criticism school and debate concerning the intentional fallacy. At outcome was the question of whether the artful intentions of the creative person in creating the work of art, any its specific form, should be associated with the criticism and evaluation of the final product of the work of fine art, or, if the work of fine art should exist evaluated on its ain merits independent of the intentions of the creative person.
In 1946, William K. Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley published a archetype and controversial New Disquisitional essay entitled "The Intentional Fallacy", in which they argued strongly against the relevance of an author'due south intention, or "intended meaning" in the analysis of a literary work. For Wimsatt and Beardsley, the words on the page were all that mattered; importation of meanings from outside the text was considered irrelevant, and potentially distracting.
In some other essay, "The Affective Fallacy," which served every bit a kind of sister essay to "The Intentional Fallacy" Wimsatt and Beardsley also discounted the reader's personal/emotional reaction to a literary work every bit a valid means of analyzing a text. This fallacy would later be repudiated past theorists from the reader-response school of literary theory. Ane of the leading theorists from this school, Stanley Fish, was himself trained by New Critics. Fish criticizes Wimsatt and Beardsley in his essay "Literature in the Reader" (1970).[forty]
As summarized by Berys Gaut and Livingston in their essay "The Creation of Art": "Structuralist and mail service-structuralists theorists and critics were sharply critical of many aspects of New Criticism, beginning with the accent on aesthetic appreciation and the and then-chosen autonomy of art, but they reiterated the attack on biographical criticisms' assumption that the artist's activities and feel were a privileged disquisitional topic."[41] These authors argue that: "Anti-intentionalists, such every bit formalists, hold that the intentions involved in the making of art are irrelevant or peripheral to correctly interpreting art. So details of the act of creating a piece of work, though perhaps of interest in themselves, accept no bearing on the correct interpretation of the work."[42]
Gaut and Livingston define the intentionalists as singled-out from formalists stating that: "Intentionalists, dissimilar formalists, hold that reference to intentions is essential in fixing the correct estimation of works." They quote Richard Wollheim every bit stating that, "The task of criticism is the reconstruction of the creative process, where the artistic process must in turn be thought of as something not stopping short of, but terminating on, the work of art itself."[42]
Derivative forms of aesthetics [edit]
A big number of derivative forms of aesthetics have developed as gimmicky and transitory forms of inquiry associated with the field of aesthetics which include the post-modern, psychoanalytic, scientific, and mathematical amongst others.
Mail-mod aesthetics and psychoanalysis [edit]
Early on-twentieth-century artists, poets and composers challenged existing notions of beauty, broadening the scope of art and aesthetics. In 1941, Eli Siegel, American philosopher and poet, founded Artful Realism, the philosophy that reality itself is aesthetic, and that "The world, art, and cocky explain each other: each is the aesthetic oneness of opposites."[43] [44]
Diverse attempts have been fabricated to define Post-Modern Aesthetics. The challenge to the assumption that dazzler was cardinal to fine art and aesthetics, thought to be original, is really continuous with older artful theory; Aristotle was the first in the Western tradition to allocate "dazzler" into types as in his theory of drama, and Kant made a distinction between dazzler and the sublime. What was new was a refusal to credit the higher status of certain types, where the taxonomy unsaid a preference for tragedy and the sublime to comedy and the Rococo.
Croce suggested that "expression" is cardinal in the way that beauty was once idea to be primal. George Dickie suggested that the sociological institutions of the fine art world were the glue binding fine art and sensibility into unities.[45] Marshall McLuhan suggested that fine art e'er functions as a "counter-environment" designed to make visible what is unremarkably invisible virtually a social club.[46] Theodor Adorno felt that aesthetics could not continue without against the part of the culture manufacture in the commodification of art and aesthetic feel. Hal Foster attempted to portray the reaction against beauty and Modernist fine art in The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. Arthur Danto has described this reaction as "kalliphobia" (after the Greek word for beauty, κάλλος kallos).[47] André Malraux explains that the notion of beauty was connected to a particular conception of art that arose with the Renaissance and was still dominant in the eighteenth century (but was supplanted later). The discipline of aesthetics, which originated in the eighteenth century, mistook this transient country of affairs for a revelation of the permanent nature of art.[48] Brian Massumi suggests to reconsider beauty post-obit the aesthetical thought in the philosophy of Deleuze and Guattari.[49] Walter Benjamin echoed Malraux in believing aesthetics was a comparatively recent invention, a view proven wrong in the late 1970s, when Abraham Moles and Frieder Nake analyzed links between dazzler, data processing, and data theory. Denis Dutton in "The Art Instinct" also proposed that an aesthetic sense was a vital evolutionary cistron.
Jean-François Lyotard re-invokes the Kantian stardom betwixt taste and the sublime. Sublime painting, different kitsch realism, "... volition enable united states to see merely by making information technology impossible to see; it will please only by causing hurting."[50] [51]
Sigmund Freud inaugurated aesthetical thinking in Psychoanalysis mainly via the "Uncanny" as aesthetical bear on.[52] Post-obit Freud and Merleau-Ponty,[53] Jacques Lacan theorized aesthetics in terms of sublimation and the Matter.[54]
The relation of Marxist aesthetics to postal service-modern aesthetics is still a contentious area of debate.
Recent aesthetics [edit]
Guy Sircello has pioneered efforts in analytic philosophy to develop a rigorous theory of aesthetics, focusing on the concepts of beauty,[55] love[56] and sublimity.[57] In contrast to romantic theorists, Sircello argued for the objectivity of beauty and formulated a theory of love on that basis.
British philosopher and theorist of conceptual fine art aesthetics, Peter Osborne, makes the point that "'post-conceptual art' aesthetic does not business organization a particular blazon of contemporary art so much as the historical-ontological condition for the production of contemporary art in general ...".[58] Osborne noted that contemporary art is 'post-conceptual' Archived 6 December 2016 at the Wayback Automobile in a public lecture delivered in 2010.
Gary Tedman has put forward a theory of a subjectless aesthetics derived from Karl Marx's concept of breach, and Louis Althusser's antihumanism, using elements of Freud'due south group psychology, defining a concept of the 'aesthetic level of practice'.[59]
Gregory Loewen has suggested that the subject is cardinal in the interaction with the aesthetic object. The work of art serves equally a vehicle for the projection of the individual's identity into the world of objects, besides equally beingness the irruptive source of much of what is uncanny in modern life. Every bit well, fine art is used to memorialize individuated biographies in a fashion that allows persons to imagine that they are part of something greater than themselves.[60]
Aesthetics and science [edit]
The field of experimental aesthetics was founded past Gustav Theodor Fechner in the 19th century. Experimental aesthetics in these times had been characterized by a field of study-based, anterior arroyo. The assay of individual experience and behaviour based on experimental methods is a fundamental part of experimental aesthetics. In item, the perception of works of art,[61] music, or modern items such as websites[62] or other IT products[63] is studied. Experimental aesthetics is strongly oriented towards the natural sciences. Modern approaches by and large come from the fields of cognitive psychology or neuroscience (neuroaesthetics[64]).
In the 1970s, Abraham Moles and Frieder Nake were among the starting time to analyze links between aesthetics, data processing, and information theory.[65] [66]
In the 1990s, Jürgen Schmidhuber described an algorithmic theory of beauty which takes the subjectivity of the observer into account and postulates: amidst several observations classified as comparable by a given subjective observer, the aesthetically most pleasing one is the one with the shortest description, given the observer'south previous cognition and his particular method for encoding the data.[67] [68] This is closely related to the principles of algorithmic information theory and minimum description length. One of his examples: mathematicians enjoy uncomplicated proofs with a short description in their formal language. Some other very concrete case describes an aesthetically pleasing homo confront whose proportions tin be described past very few $.25 of data,[69] [70] cartoon inspiration from less detailed 15th century proportion studies past Leonardo da Vinci and Albrecht Dürer. Schmidhuber's theory explicitly distinguishes between what'southward beautiful and what'south interesting, stating that interestingness corresponds to the starting time derivative of subjectively perceived beauty. Here the premise is that any observer continually tries to improve the predictability and compressibility of the observations by discovering regularities such equally repetitions and symmetries and fractal self-similarity. Whenever the observer's learning process (which may be a predictive artificial neural network; meet also Neuroesthetics) leads to improved data compression such that the observation sequence can be described by fewer bits than earlier, the temporary interestingness of the data corresponds to the number of saved bits. This pinch progress is proportional to the observer'due south internal reward, also called marvel reward. A reinforcement learning algorithm is used to maximize future expected reward by learning to execute activity sequences that cause boosted interesting input data with even so unknown but learnable predictability or regularity. The principles can be implemented on artificial agents which and so exhibit a form of artificial curiosity.[71] [72] [73] [74]
Truth in beauty and mathematics [edit]
Mathematical considerations, such as symmetry and complexity, are used for analysis in theoretical aesthetics. This is different from the aesthetic considerations of practical aesthetics used in the report of mathematical beauty. Aesthetic considerations such as symmetry and simplicity are used in areas of philosophy, such as ideals and theoretical physics and cosmology to define truth, exterior of empirical considerations. Beauty and Truth have been argued to be about synonymous,[75] as reflected in the statement "Beauty is truth, truth beauty" in the poem "Ode on a Grecian Urn" by John Keats, or by the Hindu motto "Satyam Shivam Sundaram" (Satya (Truth) is Shiva (God), and Shiva is Sundaram (Beautiful)). The fact that judgments of beauty and judgments of truth both are influenced by processing fluency, which is the ease with which information can be processed, has been presented every bit an explanation for why beauty is sometimes equated with truth.[76] Recent inquiry found that people employ dazzler every bit an indication for truth in mathematical pattern tasks.[77] Notwithstanding, scientists including the mathematician David Orrell[78] and physicist Marcelo Gleiser[79] accept argued that the accent on aesthetic criteria such as symmetry is every bit capable of leading scientists astray.
Computational approaches [edit]
Computational approaches to aesthetics emerged amid efforts to utilise computer science methods "to predict, convey, and evoke emotional response to a piece of art.[fourscore] It this field, aesthetics is not considered to be dependent on taste but is a matter of knowledge, and, consequently, learning.[81] In 1928, the mathematician George David Birkhoff created an aesthetic measure K = O/C as the ratio of order to complexity.[82]
Since about 2005, computer scientists have attempted to develop automated methods to infer aesthetic quality of images.[83] [84] [85] [86] Typically, these approaches follow a auto learning approach, where big numbers of manually rated photographs are used to "teach" a figurer about what visual properties are of relevance to aesthetic quality. A study by Y. Li and C.J. Hu employed Birkhoff'due south measurement in their statistical learning approach where order and complexity of an image determined aesthetic value.[87] The image complexity was computed using data theory while the guild was adamant using fractal compression.[87] There is also the case of the Acquine engine, developed at Penn Country University, that rates natural photographs uploaded by users.[88]
There have also been relatively successful attempts with regard to chess[ further explanation needed ] and music.[89] Computational approaches take also been attempted in moving-picture show making equally demonstrated past a software model developed by Chitra Dorai and a group of researchers at the IBM T.J. Watson Research Center.[90] The tool predicted aesthetics based on the values of narrative elements.[90] A relation between Max Bense'south mathematical formulation of aesthetics in terms of "redundancy" and "complexity" and theories of musical apprehension was offered using the notion of Data Rate.[91]
Evolutionary aesthetics [edit]
Evolutionary aesthetics refers to evolutionary psychology theories in which the basic artful preferences of Human being sapiens are argued to have evolved in guild to raise survival and reproductive success.[92] One case being that humans are argued to observe beautiful and adopt landscapes which were practiced habitats in the ancestral environment. Another example is that body symmetry and proportion are important aspects of physical attractiveness which may be due to this indicating adept health during body growth. Evolutionary explanations for aesthetical preferences are of import parts of evolutionary musicology, Darwinian literary studies, and the written report of the evolution of emotion.
Applied aesthetics [edit]
Every bit well as existence applied to art, aesthetics can as well be practical to cultural objects, such as crosses or tools. For example, artful coupling between art-objects and medical topics was made by speakers working for the United states Information Agency.[93] Art slides were linked to slides of pharmacological information, which improved attending and memory past simultaneous activation of intuitive correct brain with rational left. It tin can as well be used in topics equally diverse equally cartography, mathematics, gastronomy, fashion and website design.[94] [95] [96] [97] [98]
Criticism [edit]
The philosophy of aesthetics as a practice has been criticized by some sociologists and writers of art and society. Raymond Williams, for example, argues that at that place is no unique and or individual aesthetic object which tin be extrapolated from the art globe, but rather that there is a continuum of cultural forms and experience of which ordinary speech and experiences may betoken as art. Past "art" we may frame several artistic "works" or "creations" as then though this reference remains inside the institution or special result which creates it and this leaves some works or other possible "art" outside of the frame work, or other interpretations such as other phenomenon which may non be considered as "fine art".[99]
Pierre Bourdieu disagrees with Kant's idea of the "aesthetic". He argues that Kant's "aesthetic" merely represents an feel that is the product of an elevated course habitus and scholarly leisure as opposed to other possible and equally valid "aesthetic" experiences which lay outside Kant'southward narrow definition.[100]
Timothy Laurie argues that theories of musical aesthetics "framed entirely in terms of appreciation, contemplation or reflection risk idealizing an implausibly unmotivated listener defined solely through musical objects, rather than seeing them as a person for whom complex intentions and motivations produce variable attractions to cultural objects and practices".[101]
See also [edit]
- Philosophy portal
- Aesthetics of scientific discipline
- Art and Theosophy
- Art periods
- History of aesthetics before the 20th century
- Medieval aesthetics
- Mise en scène
- Theological aesthetics
- Theory of art
References [edit]
- ^ [1], Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 28-02-2021.
- ^ Zangwill, Nick. "Aesthetic Judgment", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 02-28-2003/10-22-2007. Retrieved 07-24-2008.
- ^ Thomas Munro, "Aesthetics", The Globe Book Encyclopedia, Vol. 1, ed. A. Richard Harmet, et al., (Chicago: Trade Mart Plaza, 1986), p. 80
- ^ Kelly (1998) p. ix
- ^ Riedel, Tom (Autumn 1999). "Review of Encyclopedia of Aesthetics 4 vol. Michael Kelly". Art Documentation: Journal of the Fine art Libraries Society of North America. xviii (ii): 48. doi:x.1086/adx.18.two.27949030.
- ^ "aesthetic – Definition of aesthetic in English by Oxford Dictionaries". Oxford Dictionaries - English . Retrieved 22 October 2017.
- ^ Harper, Douglas. "aesthetic". Online Etymology Lexicon.
- ^ Slater, Barry Hartley. "Aesthetics". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Guyer, Paul (2005). Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics . Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-60669-1.
- ^ Wilson, N (31 October 2013). Encyclopedia of Ancient Hellenic republic. Routledge. p. 20. ISBN978-1-136-78800-0. .
- ^ Barnett Newman Foundation, Chronology, 1952 Retrieved 30 August 2010
- ^ The Abuse of Beauty: Aesthetics and the Concept of Art, Past Arthur Coleman Danto, p.one, Published past Open Court Publishing, 2003, ISBN 0-8126-9540-2, 978-0-8126-9540-three
- ^ Shelley, James (2017), "The Concept of the Aesthetic", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford Academy, retrieved 9 December 2018
- ^ Thomas Munro, "aesthetics", The World Book Encyclopedia, Vol. 1, ed. A. Richard Harmet, et al., (Chicago: Merchandise Mart Plaza, 1986), p. 81.
- ^ David Hume, Essays Moral, Political, Literary, Indianapolis: Literary Fund, 1987.
- ^ Bourdieu, Pierre (1984). Distinction. Routledge. ISBN 0-674-21277-0
- ^ Zangwill, Nick (26 Baronial 2014). "Aesthetic Judgment". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^ Tatarkiewicz, Władysław (1980). A History of Six Ideas: an essay in aesthetics. PWN/Polish Scientific Publishers. ISBN9788301008246.
- ^ Meta-Aesthetics - Oxford Reference
- ^ Bezrucka, Yvonne (2017). The Invention of Northern Aesthetics in 18th-Century English Literature.
- ^ Bezrucka, Yvonne (2008). "The Well Beloved: Thomas Hardy'due south Manifesto of 'Regional Aesthetics'". Victorian Literature and Civilization. 36: 227–245. doi:10.1017/S1060150308080133. S2CID 170093813.
- ^ Holm, Ivar (2006). Ideas and Beliefs in Compages and Industrial design: How attitudes, orientations, and underlying assumptions shape the built environment. Oslo School of Compages and Design. ISBN 82-547-0174-i.
- ^ Korsmeyer, Carolyn, ed. (1998). Aesthetics: The Big Questions. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN978-0-631-20594-iv.
- ^ Susanne Grüner; Eva Specker & Helmut Leder (2019). "Effects of Context and Genuineness in the Experience of Art". Empirical Studies of the Arts. 37 (2): 138–152. doi:10.1177/0276237418822896. S2CID 150115587.
- ^ Consider Cloudless Greenberg's arguments in "On Modernist Painting" (1961), reprinted in Aesthetics: A Reader in Philosophy of Arts.
- ^ Denis Dutton's Aesthetic Universals summarized by Steven Pinker in The Blank Slate
- ^ Derek Allan, Art and the Human being Risk: André Malraux'southward Theory of Art. (Amsterdam: Rodopi. 2009)
- ^ Dewey, John. (1932)'Ethics', with James Tufts. In: The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882–1953 Edited Jo-Ann Boydston: Carbonsdale: Southern Illinois University Press. p. 275.
- ^ Peace Education – Exploring Upstanding and Philosophical Foundations Archived 29 December 2008 at the Wayback Machine infoagepub.com
- ^ S., Folio, James (2017). Peace Educational activity : Exploring Ethical and Philosophical Foundations. eprints.qut.edu.au. ISBN978-1-59311-889-1 . Retrieved 22 October 2017.
- ^ a b c d e Sartwell, Crispin (2017). "Beauty". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^ "Aesthetics". Encyclopedia Britannica . Retrieved 9 February 2021.
- ^ a b c "Beauty and Ugliness". www.encyclopedia.com . Retrieved ix Feb 2021.
- ^ Honderich, Ted (2005). "Aesthetic judgment". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford Academy Press.
- ^ a b Zangwill, Nick (2003). "Beauty". In Levinson, Jerrold (ed.). Oxford Handbook to Aesthetics. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.003.0018.
- ^ a b c De Clercq, Rafael (2013). "Beauty". The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. Routledge.
- ^ Gary Martin (2007). "Beauty is in the eye of the beholder". The Phrase Finder. Archived from the original on 30 November 2007. Retrieved four December 2007.
- ^ Gorodeisky, Keren (2019). "On Liking Aesthetic Value". Philosophy and Phenomenological Inquiry. 102 (ii): 261–280. doi:10.1111/phpr.12641. ISSN 1933-1592. S2CID 204522523.
- ^ Craig, Edward (1996). "Beauty". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.
- ^ Leitch, Vincent B., et al., eds. The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. New York: Due west.W. Norton & Company, 2001.
- ^ Gaut, Berys; Livingston, Paisley (2003). The Creation of Art. Cambridge University Printing. p. iii. ISBN978-0-521-81234-4.
- ^ a b Gaut and Livingston, p. 6.
- ^ Green, Edward (2005). "Donald Francis Tovey, Artful Realism and the Need for a Philosophic Musicology". International Review of the Aesthetics and Folklore of Music. 36 (2): 227–248. JSTOR 30032170.
- ^ Siegel, Eli (1955). "Is Beauty the Making One of Opposites?". The Periodical of Aesthetics and Fine art Criticism. fourteen (2): 282–283. JSTOR 425879.
- ^ Rex, Alexandra. "The Aesthetic Attitude". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Grosswiler, Paul (2010). Transforming McLuhan: Cultural, Critical, and Postmodern Perspectives. Peter Lang Publishing. p. 13. ISBN978-1-4331-1067-2 . Retrieved 10 March 2015.
- ^ Danto, Arthur C. (2004). "Kalliphobia in Contemporary Art". Art Journal. 63 (2): 24–35. doi:10.2307/4134518. JSTOR 4134518.
- ^ Derek Allan, Art and the Man Adventure, André Malraux's Theory of Art (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2009)
- ^ Massumi, Brian, (ed.), A Shock to Idea. Expression after Deleuze and Guattari. London & NY: Routeledge, 2002. ISBN 0-415-23804-8
- ^ Lyotard, Jean-Françoise, What is Postmodernism?, in The Postmodern Condition, Minnesota and Manchester, 1984.
- ^ Lyotard, Jean-Françoise, Scriptures: Diffracted Traces, in Theory, Culture and Society, Book 21, Number 1, 2004.
- ^ Freud, Sigmund, "The Uncanny" (1919). Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Work of Sigmund Freud, 17:234–236. London: The Hogarth Press
- ^ Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1964), "The Visible and the Invisible". Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-0457-1
- ^ Lacan, Jacques, "The Ethics of Psychoanalysis" (The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book 7), NY: Westward.W. Norton & Visitor, 1992.
- ^ Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Dazzler. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
- ^ Guy Sircello, Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Printing, 1989.
- ^ Guy Sircello, "How Is a Theory of the Sublime Possible?" The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism Vol. 51, No. 4 (Autumn, 1993), pp. 541–550
- ^ Peter Osborne, Anywhere Or Not at All: Philosophy of Contemporary Art, Verso Books, London, 2013. pp. three & 51
- ^ Tedman, G. (2012) Aesthetics & Alienation, Nothing Books
- ^ Gregory Loewen, Aesthetic Subjectivity, 2011 pp. 36–37, 157, 238)
- ^ Kobbert, M. (1986), Kunstpsychologie ("Psychology of art"), Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt
- ^ Thielsch, One thousand.T. (2008), Ästhetik von Websites. Wahrnehmung von Ästhetik und deren Beziehung zu Inhalt, Usability und Persönlichkeitsmerkmalen. ("The aesthetics of websites. Perception of aesthetics and its relation to content, usability, and personality traits."), MV Wissenschaft, Münster
- ^ Hassenzahl, M. (2008), Aesthetics in interactive products: Correlates and consequences of dazzler. In H.N.J. Schifferstein & P. Hekkert (Eds.): Product Experience. (pp. 287–302). Elsevier, Amsterdam
- ^ Martindale, C (2007). "Recent trends in the psychological study of aesthetics, inventiveness, and the arts". Empirical Studies of the Arts. 25 (2): 121–141. doi:x.2190/b637-1041-2635-16nn. S2CID 143506308.
- ^ A. Moles: Théorie de l'information et perception esthétique, Paris, Denoël, 1973 (Information Theory and aesthetical perception)
- ^ F Nake (1974). Ästhetik als Informationsverarbeitung. (Aesthetics every bit data processing). Grundlagen und Anwendungen der Informatik im Bereich ästhetischer Produktion und Kritik. Springer, 1974, ISBN 3-211-81216-four, 978-3-211-81216-7
- ^ Schmidhuber, Jürgen (22 October 1997). "Low-Complexity Art". Leonardo. 30 (2): 97–103. doi:x.2307/1576418. JSTOR 1576418. PMID 22845826. S2CID 18741604.
- ^ "Theory of Dazzler – Facial Attractiveness – Low-Complexity Art". www.idsia.ch . Retrieved 22 October 2017.
- ^ Schmidhuber, Jürgen (7 June 1998). "Facial dazzler and fractal geometry". Cogprint Archive. Archived from the original on thirty November 2012.
- ^ J. Schmidhuber. Uncomplicated Algorithmic Principles of Discovery, Subjective Beauty, Selective Attention, Curiosity & Creativity. Proc. tenth Intl. Conf. on Discovery Science (DS 2007) p. 26–38, LNAI 4755, Springer, 2007. Likewise in Proc. 18th Intl. Conf. on Algorithmic Learning Theory (ALT 2007) p. 32, LNAI 4754, Springer, 2007. Articulation invited lecture for DS 2007 and ALT 2007, Sendai, Nippon, 2007. arXiv:0709.0674
- ^ J. Schmidhuber. Curious model-building control systems. International Joint Conference on Neural Networks, Singapore, vol 2, 1458–1463. IEEE printing, 1991
- ^ J. Schmidhuber. Papers on artificial curiosity since 1990: http://world wide web.idsia.ch/~juergen/interest.html
- ^ Schmidhuber, J. (2006). "Developmental robotics, optimal bogus marvel, creativity, music, and the fine arts". Connectedness Science. eighteen (2): 173–187. doi:10.1080/09540090600768658. S2CID 2923356.
- ^ "Schmidhuber's theory of dazzler and marvel in a High german TV prove" (in German). Br-online.de. three January 2018. Archived from the original on three June 2008.
- ^ Why Dazzler Is Truth: The History of Symmetry, Ian Stewart, 2008
- ^ Reber, R; Schwarz, N; Winkielman, P (2004). "Processing fluency and aesthetic pleasure: Is beauty in the perceiver's processing feel?". Personality and Social Psychology Review. 8 (four): 364–382. doi:10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3. hdl:1956/594. PMID 15582859. S2CID 1868463.
- ^ Reber, R; Brun, Grand; Mitterndorfer, Yard (2008). "The use of heuristics in intuitive mathematical judgment". Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. xv (vi): 1174–1178. doi:10.3758/pbr.fifteen.6.1174. hdl:1956/2734. PMID 19001586. S2CID 5297500.
- ^ Orrell, David (2012). Truth or Beauty: Science and the Quest for Order. New Oasis: Yale University Press. ISBN978-0-300-18661-1.
- ^ Gleiser, Marcelo (2010). A Tear at the Edge of Creation: A Radical New Vision for Life in an Imperfect Universe. Complimentary Press. ISBN978-1-4391-0832-i.
- ^ Petrosino, Alfredo (2013). Progress in Prototype Analysis and Processing, ICIAP 2013: Naples, Italia, September 9-13, 2013, Proceedings. Heidelberg: Springer. p. 21. ISBN9783642411830.
- ^ Jahanian, Ali (2016). Quantifying Aesthetics of Visual Design Practical to Automatic Pattern. Cham: Springer. pp. 11–12. ISBN9783319314853.
- ^ Akiba, Fuminori (2013). "Preface: Natural Calculating and Computational Aesthetics". Natural Computing and Across. Proceedings in Information and Communications Technology. 6: 117–118. doi:x.1007/978-4-431-54394-7_10. ISBN978-4-431-54393-0.
- ^ Datta, R.; Joshi, D.; Li, J.; Wang, J. (2006). "Studying aesthetics in photographic images using a computational arroyo". Europ. Conf. on Calculator Vision. Springer. CiteSeerX10.1.1.81.5178. doi:10.1007/11744078_23.
- ^ Wong, L.-K.; Low, K.-L. (2009). "Saliency-enhanced prototype aesthetic classification". Int. Conf. on Prototype Processing. IEEE. doi:10.1109/ICIP.2009.5413825.
- ^ Wu, Y.; Bauckhage, C.; Thurau, C. (2010). "The good, the bad, and the ugly: predicting aesthetic image labels". Int. Conf. on Pattern Recognition. IEEE. doi:x.1109/ICPR.2010.392.
- ^ Faria, J.; Bagley, South.; Rueger, Southward.; Breckon, T.P. (2013). "Challenges of Finding Aesthetically Pleasing Images" (PDF). Proc. International Workshop on Image and Audio Analysis for Multimedia Interactive Services. IEEE. Retrieved nineteen June 2013.
- ^ a b Chio, Cecilia Di; Brabazon, Anthony; Ebner, Marc; Farooq, Muddassar; Fink, Andreas; Grahl, Jörn; Greenfield, Gary; Machado, Penousal; O'Neill, Michael (2010). Applications of Evolutionary Computation: EvoApplications 2010: EvoCOMNET, EvoENVIRONMENT, EvoFIN, EvoMUSART, and EvoTRANSLOG, Istanbul, Turkey, April 7-9, 2010, Proceedings. Berlin: Springer Scientific discipline & Business organization Media. p. 302. ISBN9783642122415.
- ^ "Aesthetic Quality Inference Engine – Instant Impersonal Cess of Photos". Penn Country University. Archived from the original on 9 May 2009. Retrieved 21 June 2009.
- ^ Manaris, B., Roos, P., Penousal, M., Krehbiel, D., Pellicoro, L. and Romero, J.; A Corpus-Based Hybrid Approach to Music Analysis and Composition; Proceedings of 22nd Conference on Bogus Intelligence (AAAI-07); Vancouver, BC; 839–845 2007.
- ^ a b Hammoud, Riad (21 Jan 2007). Interactive Video: Algorithms and Technologies. Berlin: Springer Scientific discipline & Business Media. p. 162. ISBN9783540332145.
- ^ Dubnov, S.; Musical Information Dynamics as Models of Auditory Anticipation; in Machine Audition: Principles, Algorithms and Systems, Ed. W. Weng, IGI Global publication, 2010.
- ^ Shimura, Arthur P.; Palmer, Stephen E. (2012). Aesthetic Science: Connecting Minds, Brains, and Experience. Oxford Academy Press. p. 279.
- ^ Giannini AJ (December 1993). "Tangential symbols: using visual symbolization to teach pharmacological principles of drug addiction to international audiences". Journal of Clinical Pharmacology. 33 (12): 1139–1146. doi:10.1002/j.1552-4604.1993.tb03913.x. PMID 7510314. S2CID 32304779.
- ^ Kent, Alexander (2019). "Maps, Materiality and Tactile Aesthetics". The Cartographic Journal. 56 (one): 1–3. doi:10.1080/00087041.2019.1601932.
- ^ Kent, Alexander (2005). "Aesthetics: A Lost Crusade in Cartographic Theory?". The Cartographic Journal. 42 (2): 182–188. doi:x.1179/000870405X61487. S2CID 129910488.
- ^ Moshagen, M.; Thielsch, M.T. (2010). "Facets of visual aesthetics". International Journal of Man-Computer Studies. 68 (x): 689–709. doi:10.1016/j.ijhcs.2010.05.006.
- ^ Visual Aesthetics. Interaction-blueprint.org. Retrieved 31 July 2012.
- ^ Lavie, T.; Tractinsky, Northward. (2004). "Assessing dimensions of perceived visual aesthetics of web sites". International Periodical of Human being-Calculator Studies. 60 (3): 269–298. doi:x.1016/j.ijhcs.2003.09.002.
- ^ Raymond Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford Univ. Press, 1977), 155. ISBN 9780198760610
- ^ Pierre Bourdieu, "Postscript", in Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste (London: Routledge, 1984), 485-500. ISBN 9780674212770; and David Harris, "Leisure and Higher Education", in Tony Blackshaw, ed., Routledge Handbook of Leisure Studies (London: Routledge, 2013), 403. ISBN 9781136495588 and books.google.com/books?id=gc2_zubEovgC&pg=PT403
- ^ Laurie, Timothy (2014). "Music Genre as Method". Cultural Studies Review. 20 (2). doi:10.5130/csr.v20i2.4149.
Further reading [edit]
- Mario Perniola, 20th Century Aesthetics. Towards A Theory of Feeling, translated by Massimo Verdicchio, London, New Delhi, New York, Sydney: Bloomsbury, 2013, ISBN 978-1-4411-1850-9.
- Chung-yuan, Chang (1963–1970). Inventiveness and Taoism, A Study of Chinese Philosophy, Art, and Poetry. New York: Harper Torchbooks. ISBN978-0-06-131968-6.
- Handbook of Phenomenological Aesthetics. Edited by Hans Rainer Sepp and Lester Embree. (Serial: Contributions To Phenomenology, Vol. 59) Springer, Dordrecht / Heidelberg / London / New York 2010. ISBN 978-90-481-2470-1
- Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Printing, 1997.
- Ayn Rand, The Romantic Manifesto: A Philosophy of Literature, New York, NY, New American Library, 1971
- Derek Allan, Fine art and the Human Adventure, Andre Malraux'due south Theory of Art, Rodopi, 2009
- Derek Allan. Art and Time, Cambridge Scholars, 2013.
- Augros, Robert M., Stanciu, George N., The New Story of Science: mind and the universe, Lake Bluff, Ill.: Regnery Gateway, 1984. ISBN 0-89526-833-vii (has significant material on Art, Science and their philosophies)
- John Bough and Gene Blocker, Contemporary Philosophy of Art: Readings in Analytic Aesthetics 1993.
- René Bergeron. L'Art et sa spiritualité. Québec, QC.: Éditions du Pelican, 1961.
- Christine Buci-Glucksmann (2003), Esthétique de l'éphémère, Galilée. (French)
- Noël Carroll (2000), Theories of Art Today, University of Wisconsin Press.
- Mario Costa (1999) (in Italian), Fifty'estetica dei media. Avanguardie e tecnologia, Milan: Castelvecchi, ISBN 88-8210-165-vii.
- Benedetto Croce (1922), Aesthetic as Scientific discipline of Expression and General Linguistic.
- Eastward.S. Dallas (1866), The Gay Scientific discipline, ii volumes, on the aesthetics of poetry.
- Danto, Arthur (2003), The Abuse of Dazzler: Aesthetics and the Concept of Fine art, Open Court.
- Stephen Davies (1991), Definitions of Art.
- Terry Eagleton (1990), The Ideology of the Artful. Blackwell. ISBN 0-631-16302-6
- Susan 50. Feagin and Patrick Maynard (1997), Aesthetics. Oxford Readers.
- Penny Florence and Nicola Foster (eds.) (2000), Differential Aesthetics. London: Ashgate. ISBN 0-7546-1493-X
- Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes (eds.), Routledge Companion to Aesthetics. 3rd edition. London and New York: Routledge, 2013.
- Annemarie Gethmann-Siefert (1995), Einführung in die Ästhetik, Munich, West. Fink.
- David Goldblatt and Lee B. Brown, ed. (2010), Aesthetics: A Reader in the Philosophy of the Arts. 3rd edition. Pearson Publishing.
- Theodore Gracyk (2011), The Philosophy of Art: An Introduction. Polity Press.
- Greenberg, Clement (1960), "Modernist Painting", The Collected Essays and Criticism 1957–1969, The University of Chicago Press, 1993, 85–92.
- Evelyn Hatcher (ed.), Fine art as Culture: An Introduction to the Anthropology of Art. 1999
- Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1975), Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T.Thou. Knox, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Hans Hofmann and Sara T Weeks; Bartlett H Hayes; Addison Gallery of American Fine art; Search for the real, and other essays (Cambridge, Massachusetts, M.I.T. Printing, 1967) OCLC 1125858
- Michael Ann Holly and Keith Moxey (eds.), Fine art History and Visual Studies. Yale University Press, 2002. ISBN 0-300-09789-1
- Carol Armstrong and Catherine de Zegher (eds.), Women Artists at the Millennium. Massachusetts: October Books/MIT Press, 2006. ISBN 0-262-01226-10
- Kant, Immanuel (1790), Critique of Judgement, Translated by Werner S. Pluhar, Hackett Publishing Co., 1987.
- Kelly, Michael (Editor in Chief) (1998) Encyclopedia of Aesthetics. New York, Oxford, Oxford Academy Press. 4 vol. pp. xvii–521, pp. 555, pp. 536, pp. 572; 2224 total pages; 100 b/due west photos; ISBN 978-0-19-511307-5. Covers philosophical, historical, sociological, and biographical aspects of Art and Aesthetics worldwide.
- Kent, Alexander J. (2005). "Aesthetics: A Lost Cause in Cartographic Theory?". The Cartographic Periodical. 42 (2): 182–188. doi:ten.1179/000870405x61487. S2CID 129910488.
- Søren Kierkegaard (1843), Either/Or, translated by Alastair Hannay, London, Penguin, 1992
- Peter Kivy (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aesthetics. 2004
- Carolyn Korsmeyer (ed.), Aesthetics: The Big Questions. 1998
- Lyotard, Jean-François (1979), The Postmodern Condition, Manchester University Press, 1984.
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (1969), The Visible and the Invisible, Northwestern University Press.
- David Novitz (1992), The Boundaries of Fine art.
- Mario Perniola, The Fine art and Its Shadow, foreword past Hugh J. Silverman, translated by Massimo Verdicchio, London-New York, Continuum, 2004.
- Griselda Pollock, "Does Art Call up?" In: Dana Arnold and Margaret Iverson (eds.) Art and Idea. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2003. 129–174. ISBN 0-631-22715-half dozen.
- Griselda Pollock, Encounters in the Virtual Feminist Museum: Fourth dimension, Infinite and the Archive. Routledge, 2007. ISBN 0-415-41374-5.
- Griselda Pollock, Generations and Geographies in the Visual Arts. Routledge, 1996. ISBN 0-415-14128-1.
- George Santayana (1896), The Sense of Beauty. Being the Outlines of Aesthetic Theory. New York, Modern Library, 1955.
- Elaine Scarry, On Beauty and Being Merely. Princeton, 2001. ISBN 978-0-691-08959-ane
- Friedrich Schiller, (1795), On the Aesthetic Education of Human being. Dover Publications, 2004.
- Alan Singer and Allen Dunn (eds.), Literary Aesthetics: A Reader. Blackwell Publishing Limited, 2000. ISBN 978-0-631-20869-3
- Jadranka Skorin-Kapov, The Intertwining of Aesthetics and Ideals: Exceeding of Expectations, Ecstasy, Sublimity. Lexington Books, 2016. ISBN 978-1-4985-2456-8
- Władysław Tatarkiewicz, A History of Vi Ideas: an Essay in Aesthetics, The Hague, 1980. ISBN 978-90-247-2233-4
- Władysław Tatarkiewicz, History of Aesthetics, 3 vols. (1–two, 1970; three, 1974), The Hague, Mouton.
- Markand Thakar Looking for the 'Harp' Quartet: An Investigation into Musical Beauty. University of Rochester Press, 2011.
- Leo Tolstoy, What Is Art?, Penguin Classics, 1995.
- Roger Scruton, Beauty: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford Academy Press, 2009. ISBN 0199229759
- Roger Scruton, The Aesthetic Understanding: Essays in the Philosophy of Art and Culture (1983) ISBN 1890318027
- The London Philosophy Written report Guide Archived 23 September 2009 at the Wayback Machine offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Aesthetics Archived 23 June 2011 at the Wayback Machine
- John Thousand. Valentine, Beginning Aesthetics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art. McGraw-Loma, 2006. ISBN 978-0-07-353754-2
- von Vacano, Diego, "The Fine art of Power: Machiavelli, Nietzsche and the Making of Aesthetic Political Theory," Lanham Doc: Lexington: 2007.
- Thomas Wartenberg, The Nature of Art. 2006.
- John Whitehead, Grasping for the Air current. 2001.
- Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures on aesthetics, psychology and religious belief, Oxford, Blackwell, 1966.
- Richard Wollheim, Art and its objects, second edn, 1980, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-29706-0
- Gino Zaccaria, The Enigma of Art, Leiden-Boston: Brill, 2021 https://brill.com/view/title/59609
Indian aesthetics [edit]
- Wallace Dace (1963). "The Concept of "Rasa" in Sanskrit Dramatic Theory". Educational Theatre Periodical. 15 (three): 249–254. doi:10.2307/3204783. JSTOR 3204783.
- René Daumal (1982). Rasa, or, Cognition of the cocky: essays on Indian aesthetics and selected Sanskrit studies. ISBN978-0-8112-0824-half-dozen.
- Natalia Lidova (2014). Natyashastra. Oxford University Printing. doi:10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0071.
- Natalia Lidova (1994). Drama and Ritual of Early Hinduism. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN978-81-208-1234-v.
- Ananda Lal (2004). The Oxford Companion to Indian Theatre. Oxford University Press. ISBN978-0-nineteen-564446-iii.
- Tarla Mehta (1995). Sanskrit Play Production in Ancient India. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN978-81-208-1057-0.
- Rowell, Lewis (2015). Music and Musical Thought in Early India. University of Chicago Press. ISBN978-0-226-73034-9.
- Emmie Te Nijenhuis (1974). Indian Music: History and Structure. BRILL Academic. ISBN978-ninety-04-03978-0.
- Farley P. Richmond; Darius L. Swann; Phillip B. Zarrilli (1993). Indian Theatre: Traditions of Performance. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN978-81-208-0981-ix.
- Kapila Vatsyayan (2001). Bharata, the Nāṭyaśāstra. Sahitya Akademi. ISBN978-81-260-1220-six.
- Kapila Vatsyayan (1974). Indian classical dance. Sangeet Natak Akademi. OCLC 2238067.
- Kapila Vatsyayan (2008). Aesthetic theories and forms in Indian tradition. Munshiram Manoharlal. ISBN978-81-87586-35-7. OCLC 286469807.
External links [edit]
- Aesthetics at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- Aesthetics at PhilPapers
- "Aesthetics". Cyberspace Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Aesthetics in Continental Philosophy article in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Medieval Theories of Aesthetics article in the Cyberspace Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Revue online Appareil
- Postscript 1980– Some Old Bug in New Perspectives
- Aesthetics in Art Instruction: A Expect Toward Implementation
- More than about Art, civilisation and Education
- An history of aesthetics
- The Concept of the Aesthetic
- Aesthetics entry in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Philosophy of Aesthetics entry in the Philosophy Archive
- Washington State Lath for Community & Technical Colleges: Introduction to Aesthetics
- Art Perception Complete pdf version of art historian David Cycleback's book.
- Dazzler, BBC Radio 4 discussion with Angie Hobbs, Susan James & Julian Baggini (In Our Time, 19 May 2005)
Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aesthetics
0 Response to "Which Individuals Are Credited With Introducing the Concept of a Universal Gaze in Art? Anthro"
Post a Comment